Advertisement

profile/8765IMG_20200701_011329_857.jpg
Centfranzy
MOTHER, DAUGHTERS KIDNAPPED IN KADUNA ON INDEPENDENCE DAY.
~0.4 mins read
A married woman and two of her daughters have been reportedly kidnapped from their residence in Kaduna State.


The wife and two daughters of the former Chairman of NURTW, Kaduna State branch, Alhaji Alhassan Haruna, were kidnapped in Mando area of Kaduna town on the night of October 1, 2020.



The Kaduna State Police Command spokesperson, Muhammad Jalige, could not respond when contacted over the incident.

However, a series of posts on Twitter by Senator Shehu Sani confirmed the incident.

It was gathered that the victims were still in captivity.
profile/6781FB_IMG_1568668550374.jpg
Rhoddyken
Secondus: Atiku Can Still Contest 2023 Presidential Election
~2.0 mins read
The Peoples Democratic Party (PDP) has said that the party’s floor is open for any contender willing to contest for the presidential election in 2023, including Atiku Abubakar.

National Chairman of the Party, Prince Uche Secondus, said this while reacting to questions from journalists in Bauchi Friday night on whether the party will re-present the former Vice President Atiku Abubakar who lost the 2019 presidential election to Muhammadu Buhari.

“There is no room for discrimination,” Secondus said in Bauchi State during a solidarity visit on Governor Bala Mohammed.

“Everyone is qualified; both young, old, governors, non-governors are qualified to contest and we have the space for everyone–if you win, you become our candidate. The door is open to everybody.”

In Bauchi with Secondus were Governor Aminu Tambuwal of Sokoto State, former governor of Gombe State Hassan Ibrahim Dankwambo, former Senate President David Mark and a party chieftain; Nazif Gamawa.

While reacting to the recent defections of the party members to other parties, including Former Speaker Yakubu Dogara, Secondus said anyone could leave the party but was optimistic about their return.

“It has happened before, they will move and they would come back, that’s the assurance I’m giving to you,” Secondus said.

Dogara’s fall out, according to him, was caused by alleged mismanagement of public funds and unfulfilled campaign promises.
profile/5794Screenshot_20200205-175025_1580921494282.png
Trisha
McDonald's New Spicy Chicken McNuggets Are On The Verge Of Selling Out
~2.1 mins read


McDonald's new Spicy Chicken McNuggets are on the verge of selling out
The new nuggets are being offered for a limited time.
McDonald's introduced Spicy Chicken McNuggets, Mighty Hot Sauce and the Chips Ahoy! McFlurry last month.
McDonald's introduced Spicy Chicken McNuggets, Mighty Hot Sauce and the Chips Ahoy! McFlurry last month.McDonald's
Oct. 3, 2020, 8:15 PM WAT / Source: TODAY
By Ronnie Koenig
When it comes to spicy, McDonald's customers are apparently lovin' it!

On Sept. 16, the fast food chain debuted their new Spicy Chicken McNuggets along with Mighty Hot Sauce and the Chips Ahoy! McFlurry ("to give fans the sweet, cool relief they might need") nationwide. And although the spicy items have only been out for two weeks, they're already selling out in many restaurants, which is clearly a testimony to people's hunger for hotter than usual foods.

Back in August, McDonald's teased the release of the Spicy Chicken McNuggets on Instagram, calling it "the hottest news you'll see on your feed today."


https://www.instagram.com/p/CEUWt6IppZs/

Watch TODAY All Day! Get the best news, information and inspiration from TODAY, all day long.

The Spicy Chicken McNuggets are the first new flavor of nuggets to be added to the McDonald's lineup since Chicken McNuggets made their debut on the menu back in 1983. "The new dipping sauce is both our first new sauce innovation since 2017 and the hottest one available at McDonald’s. Trust us – you’re going to want to take a dip," read McDonald's press release.

People were excited to spice up their fast food life, but as the items started quickly selling out, they made no bones about airing their grievances.

"Our McDonalds never has the spicy sauce," one customer complained on Instagram.

That guest was not alone in their frustrations. Others on Twitter spoke out about the hot sauce being unavailable.

“We’re out of Mighty Hot sauce” is the new “Our Ice cream machine is broken”

— WI9LL - Will (@WI9LL_Will) September 30, 2020
"'We’re out of Mighty Hot sauce' is the new 'Our Ice cream machine is broken,'" tweeted one humorous hot sauce lover.

And while customers may be lamenting the fact that they can't easily find these limited-time only menu items, their popularity is definitely a sign that they are a success — which could lead to them making a comeback in the future.

“McDonald's fans across the country are loving the new Spicy Chicken McNuggets, Mighty Hot Sauce and Chips Ahoy! McFlurry we introduced earlier this month, and we’re thrilled with the positive response to these limited-time offerings," McDonald's USA said in a statement emailed to TODAY Food. "If our customers truly can’t get enough, there’s always a chance we’ll bring limited-time menu items back in the future. You never know, you might just see some of these fan-favorites again soon ...”


profile/92481597753291369.jpg
Joyfrank
LIFE
~11.6 mins read

Many major historical figures in philosophy have provided an answer to the question of what, if anything, makes life meaningful, although they typically have not put it in these terms. Consider, for instance, Aristotle on the human function, Aquinas on the beatific vision, and Kant on the highest good. While these concepts have some bearing on happiness and morality, they are straightforwardly construed as accounts of which final ends a person ought to realize in order to have a life that matters. Despite the venerable pedigree, it is only in the last 50 years or so that something approaching a distinct field on the meaning of life has been established in Anglo-American philosophy, and it is only in the last 30 years that debate with real depth has appeared. Concomitant with the demise of positivism and of utilitarianism in the post-war era has been the rise of analytical enquiry into non-hedonistic conceptions of value, including conceptions of meaning in life, grounded on relatively uncontroversial (but not certain or universally shared) judgments of cases, often called “intuitions.” English-speaking philosophers can be expected to continue to find life's meaning of interest as they increasingly realize that it is a distinct topic that admits of rational enquiry to no less a degree than more familiar ethical categories such as well-being, virtuous character, and right action.

This survey critically discusses approaches to meaning in life that are prominent in contemporary Anglo-American philosophical literature. To provide context, sometimes it mentions other texts, e.g., in Continental philosophy or from before the 20th century. However, the central aim is to acquaint the reader with recent analytic work on life's meaning and to pose questions about it that are currently worthy of consideration.

When the topic of the meaning of life comes up, people often pose one of two questions: “So, what is the meaning of life?” and “What are you talking about?” The literature can be divided in terms of which question it seeks to answer. This discussion starts off with works that address the latter, abstract question regarding the sense of talk of “life's meaning,” i.e., that aim to clarify what we are asking when we pose the question of what, if anything, makes life meaningful. Afterward, it considers texts that provide answers to the more substantive question about the nature of meaning as a property. Some accounts of what make life meaningful provide particular ways to do so, e.g., by making certain achievements (James 2005), developing moral character (Thomas 2005), or learning from relationships with family members (Velleman 2005). However, most recent discussions of meaning in life are attempts to capture in a single principle all the variegated conditions that can confer meaning on life. This survey focuses heavily on the articulation and evaluation of these theories of what would make life meaningful. It concludes by examining nihilist views that the conditions necessary for meaning in life do not obtain for any of us, i.e., that all our lives are meaningless.

1. The Meaning of “Meaning”

One part of the field of life's meaning consists of the systematic attempt to clarify what people mean when they ask in virtue of what life has meaning. This section addresses different accounts of the sense of talk of “life's meaning” (and of “significance,” “importance,” and other synonyms). A large majority of those writing on life's meaning deem talk of it centrally to indicate a positive final value that an individual's life can exhibit. That is, comparatively few believe either that a meaningful life is a merely neutral quality, or that what is of key interest is the meaning of the human species or universe as a whole (for discussions focused on the latter, see Edwards 1972; Munitz 1986; Seachris 2009). Most in the field have ultimately wanted to know whether and how the existence of one of us over time has meaning, a certain property that is desirable for its own sake.

Beyond drawing the distinction between the life of an individual and that of a whole, there has been very little discussion of life as the logical bearer of meaning. For instance, is the individual's life best understood biologically, qua human being, or instead as the existence of a person that may or may not be human (Flanagan 1996)? And if an individual is loved from afar, can it logically affect the meaningfulness of her “life” (Brogaard and Smith 2005, 449)?

Returning to topics on which there is consensus, most writing on meaning believe that it comes in degrees such that some periods of life are more meaningful than others and that some lives as a whole are more meaningful than others (perhaps contra Britton 1969, 192). Note that one can coherently hold the view that some people's lives are less meaningful than others, or even meaningless, and still maintain that people have an equal moral status. Consider a consequentialist view according to which each individual counts for one in virtue of having a capacity for a meaningful life (cf. Railton 1984), or a Kantian view that says that people have an intrinsic worth in virtue of their capacity for autonomous choices, where meaning is a function of the exercise of this capacity (Nozick 1974, ch. 3). On both views, morality could counsel an agent to help people with relatively meaningless lives, at least if the condition is not of their choosing.

Another uncontroversial element of the sense of “meaningfulness” is that it connotes a good that is conceptually distinct from happiness or rightness (something emphasized in Wolf 2010). First, to ask whether someone's life is meaningful is not one and the same as asking whether her life is happy or pleasant. A life in an experience or virtual reality machine could conceivably be happy but very few take it to be a prima facie candidate for meaningfulness (Nozick 1974: 42–45). Indeed, many would say that talk of “meaning” by definition excludes the possibility of it coming from time spent in an experience machine (although there have been a small handful who disagree and contend that a meaningful life just is a pleasant life. Goetz 2012, in particular, bites many bullets.) Furthermore, one's life logically could become meaningful precisely by sacrificing one's happiness, e.g., by helping others at the expense of one's self-interest.

Second, asking whether a person's existence is significant is not identical to considering whether she has been morally upright; there seem to be ways to enhance meaning that have nothing to do with morality, at least impartially conceived, for instance, making a scientific discovery.

Of course, one might argue that a life would be meaningless if (or even because) it were unhappy or immoral, particularly given Aristotelian conceptions of these disvalues. However, that is to posit a synthetic, substantive relationship between the concepts, and is far from indicating that speaking of “meaning in life” is analytically a matter of connoting ideas regarding happiness or rightness, which is what I am denying here. My point is that the question of what makes a life meaningful is conceptually distinct from the question of what makes a life happy or moral, even if it turns out that the best answer to the question of meaning appeals to an answer to one of these other evaluative questions.

If talk about meaning in life is not by definition talk about happiness or rightness, then what is it about? There is as yet no consensus in the field. One answer is that a meaningful life is one that by definition has achieved choice-worthy purposes (Nielsen 1964) or involves satisfaction upon having done so (Hepburn 1965; Wohlgennant 1981). However, for such an analysis to clearly demarcate meaningfulness from happiness, it would be useful to modify it to indicate which purposes are germane to the former. On this score, some suggest that conceptual candidates for grounding meaning are purposes that not only have a positive value, but also render a life coherent (Markus 2003), make it intelligible (Thomson 2003, 8–13), or transcend animal nature (Levy 2005).

Now, it might be that a focus on any kind of purpose is too narrow for ruling out the logical possibility that meaning could inhere in certain actions, experiences, states, or relationships that have not been adopted as ends and willed and that perhaps even could not be, e.g., being an immortal offshoot of an unconscious, spiritual force that grounds the physical universe, as in Hinduism. In addition, the above purpose-based analyses exclude as not being about life's meaning some of the most widely read texts that purport to be about it, namely, Jean-Paul Sartre's (1948) existentialist account of meaning being constituted by whatever one chooses, and Richard Taylor's (1970, ch. 18) discussion of Sisyphus being able to acquire meaning in his life merely by having his strongest desires satisfied. These are prima facie accounts of meaning in life, but do not essentially involve the attainment of purposes that foster coherence, intelligibility or transcendence.

The latter problem also faces the alternative suggestion that talk of “life's meaning” is not necessarily about purposes, but is rather just a matter of referring to goods that are qualitatively superior, worthy of love and devotion, and appropriately awed (Taylor 1989, ch. 1). It is implausible to think that these criteria are satisfied by subjectivist appeals to whatever choices one ends up making or to whichever desires happen to be strongest for a given person.

Although relatively few have addressed the question of whether there exists a single, primary sense of “life's meaning,” the inability to find one so far might suggest that none exists. In that case, it could be that the field is united in virtue of addressing certain overlapping but not equivalent ideas that have family resemblances (Metz 2013, ch. 2). Perhaps when we speak of “meaning in life,” we have in mind one or more of these related ideas: certain conditions that are worthy of great pride or admiration, values that warrant devotion and love, qualities that make a life intelligible, or ends apart from base pleasure that are particularly choice-worthy. Another possibility is that talk of “meaning in life” fails to exhibit even this degree of unity, and is instead a grab-bag of heterogenous ideas (Mawson 2010; Oakley 2010).

As the field reflects more on the sense of “life's meaning,” it should not only try to ascertain in what respect it admits of unity, but also try to differentiate the concept of life's meaning from other, closely related ideas. For instance, the concept of a worthwhile life is probably not identical to that of a meaningful one (Baier 1997, ch. 5; Metz 2012). For instance, one would not be conceptually confused to claim that a meaningless life full of animal pleasures would be worth living. Furthermore, it seems that talk of a “meaningless life” does not simply connote the concept of an absurd (Nagel 1970; Feinberg 1980), unreasonable (Baier 1997, ch. 5), futile (Trisel 2002), or wasted (Kamm 2003, 210–14) life.

Fortunately the field does not need an extremely precise analysis of the concept of life's meaning (or definition of the phrase “life's meaning”) in order to make progress on the substantive question of what life's meaning is. Knowing that meaningfulness analytically concerns a variable and gradient final good in a person's life that is conceptually distinct from happiness, rightness, and worthwhileness provides a certain amount of common ground. The rest of this discussion addresses attempts to theoretically capture the nature of this good.

2. Supernaturalism

Most English speaking philosophers writing on meaning in life are trying to develop and evaluate theories, i.e., fundamental and general principles that are meant to capture all the particular ways that a life could obtain meaning. These theories are standardly divided on a metaphysical basis, i.e., in terms of which kinds of properties are held to constitute the meaning. Supernaturalist theories are views that meaning in life must be constituted by a certain relationship with a spiritual realm. If God or a soul does not exist, or if they exist but one fails to have the right relationship with them, then supernaturalism—or the Western version of it (on which I focus)—entails that one's life is meaningless. In contrast, naturalist theories are views that meaning can obtain in a world as known solely by science. Here, although meaning could accrue from a divine realm, certain ways of living in a purely physical universe would be sufficient for it. Note that there is logical space for a non-naturalist theory that meaning is a function of abstract properties that are neither spiritual nor physical. However, only scant attention has been paid to this possibility in the Anglo-American literature (Williams 1999; Audi 2005).

Supernaturalist thinkers in the monotheistic tradition are usefully divided into those with God-centered views and soul-centered views. The former take some kind of connection with God (understood to be a spiritual person who is all-knowing, all-good, and all-powerful and who is the ground of the physical universe) to constitute meaning in life, even if one lacks a soul (construed as an immortal, spiritual substance). The latter deem having a soul and putting it into a certain state to be what makes life meaningful, even if God does not exist. Of course, many supernaturalists believe that certain relationships with God and a soul are jointly necessary and sufficient for a significant existence. However, the simpler view is common, and often arguments proffered for the more complex view fail to support it any more than the simpler view.

2.1 God-centered Views

The most widely held and influential God-based account of meaning in life is that one's existence is more significant, the better one fulfills a purpose God has assigned. The familiar idea is that God has a plan for the universe and that one's life is meaningful to the degree that one helps God realize this plan, perhaps in the particular way God wants one to do so (Affolter 2007). Fulfilling God's purpose by choice is the sole source of meaning, with the existence of an afterlife not necessary for it (Brown 1971; Levine 1987; Cottingham 2003). If a person failed to do what God intends him to do with his life, then, on the current view, his life would be meaningless.

What I call “purpose theorists” differ over what it is about God's purpose that makes it uniquely able to confer meaning on human lives. Some argue that God's purpose could be the sole source of invariant moral rules, where a lack of such would render our lives nonsensical (Craig 1994; Cottingham 2003). However, Euthyphro problems arguably plague this rationale; God's purpose for us must be of a particular sort for our lives to obtain meaning by fulfilling it (as is often pointed out, serving as food for intergalactic travelers won't do), which suggests that there is a standard external to God's purpose that determines what the content of God's purpose ought to be (but see Cottingham 2005, ch. 3). In addition, some critics argue that a universally applicable and binding moral code is not necessary for meaning in life, even if the act of helping others is (Ellin 1995, 327).

Other purpose theorists contend that having been created by God for a reason would be the only way that our lives could avoid being contingent (Craig 1994; cf. Haber 1997). But it is unclear whether God's arbitrary will would avoid contingency, or whether his non-arbitrary will would avoid contingency anymore than a deterministic physical world. Furthermore, the literature is still unclear what contingency is and why it is a deep problem. Still other purpose theorists maintain that our lives would have meaning only insofar as they were intentionally fashioned by a creator, thereby obtaining meaning of the sort that an art-object has (Gordon 1983). Here, though, freely choosing to do any particular thing would not be necessary for meaning, and everyone's life would have an equal degree of meaning, which are both counterintuitive implications (see Trisel 2012 for additional criticisms). Are all these objections sound? Is there a promising reason for thinking that fulfilling God's (as opposed to any human's) purpose is what constitutes meaning in life?

Not only does each of these versions of the purpose theory have specific problems, but they all face this shared objection: if God assigned us a purpose, then God would degrade us and thereby undercut the possibility of us obtaining meaning from fulfilling the purpose (Baier 1957, 118–20; Murphy 1982, 14–15; Singer 1996, 29). This objection goes back at least to Jean-Paul Sartre (1948, 45), and there are many replies to it in the literature that have yet to be assessed (e.g., Hepburn 1965, 271–73; Brown 1971, 20–21; Davis 1986, 155–56; Hanfling 1987, 45–46; Moreland 1987, 129; Walker 1989; Jacquette 2001, 20–21).

profile/3690IMG-20200925-WA0011.jpg
Amygold
Moringa’s Benefits On Sexual Performance And Fertility
~4.1 mins read

Moringa (scientifically known as moringa pterygosperma) is one of the world’s most popular superfoods because of its endless nutrients and health benefits. Moringa has been said to have properties that can do everything from preventing cancer to losing weight. 

You may be surprised to find out that Moringa can also help spice up your sex life! How? You may wonder, well, there are several benefits that Moringa can have on your sex life, the high levels of vitamins and minerals have been known to enhance bodily functions and enhance sex hormones. 

Moringa Sex Benefits

a man and a woman are kissing on the water

 

Intense Love

Trying Moringa could change your life and could benefit your sex life too. We’ve put together this article to go over some of the benefits of moringa on sexual performance and Fertility. 

Let’s talk about the facts! Moringa is full of vitamins, minerals, and nutrients. Studies have shown that the high levels of Vitamin C, A, and D in Moringa seeds can lead to enhanced hormone levels in men. These three vitamins combined attest to the sexual benefits of moringa. 

Vitamin C helps to make your immune system stronger, which leads to increased sexual stamina and stronger erections. Some people wonder if moringa increases blood flow, it does. Vitamin C also helps to regulate blood flow which in turn creates healthy circulation and blood flow to the penis. 

Vitamin A is an important nutrient in sperm production and virility. 

Vitamin D is important for energy and testosterone building. A healthy intake of vitamin D leads to strong long-lasting erections in men. The effects of taking moringa could lead to a long moringa sex drive. Vitamin D contains Saponin, a chemical that can enhance sex hormones and increases testosterone levels in men. 

Moringa’s natural properties can increase sperm count and moringa can help with sperm production. Minerals like iron, calcium, and zinc are all present in moringa, these minerals are major factors in the connection between moringa and sperm production. 

Moringa’s sex benefits are endless. The seeds of moringa have been used to treat erectile dysfunction and other sexual virility issues.

Moringa As A Libido Booster

moringa tree and seedpods

 

Moringa Tree And Seedpods

Many people wonder if moringa can increase libido. Others ask “Is Moringa an aphrodisiac? The answer to both of those questions is yes! 

Libido is your sexual desire and an aphrodisiac is a food, drink, or drug that stimulates sexual desire. 

Studies have shown that Moringa’s sexual benefits make moringa a libido booster and an aphrodisiac. Some ask if the moringa increases blood flow. The vitamins and minerals in moringa seeds increase blood flow to the penis and help with enhancing the hardness and size of an erection and increasing overall health.

Moringa has also shown to help decrease the stress hormone that causes erectile and sexual dysfunction in men. The vitamins in moringa are essential for sexual arousal.

The leaf extracts of moringa produce androgenic effects which enhance sexual drive and increase increases the health of sexual organs. 

Moringa Side Effects On Fertility

a pregnant woman does yoga and moringa powder

 

Moringa Helps With Fertility

If you or your partner are considering using moringa during pregnancy it’s recommended that you discuss it with your doctor first. There have been close to no side effects reported from moringa, but some sources say that moringa may possess anti-fertility qualities. Pregnant women or women who are trying to get pregnant are recommended to carefully watch their dosage when taking moringa. 

After consulting your doctor, moringa leaves can actually be very helpful pre, post, and during pregnancy. Moringa tea and fertility have been connected due to the potassium, zinc, and abundance of nutrients in the plant. The nutrients in moringa can help a woman have a healthy pregnancy.

There are several moringa benefits for fertility and most medical professionals say there are no negative side effects of taking moringa during pregnancy.  

Moringa is a natural substance rich in vitamins and minerals that are good for your overall health, your reproductive health, and your sexual health.  

Source: Insidemoringa

profile/9083IMG_20200816_194234.jpg
Chidexstar
Suspected Political Thugs Being Kept At Ondo Hotel, Group Alleges
~1.5 mins read

The Rule of Law And Accountability Advocacy Centre has raised the alarm over the presence of suspected political thugs at Sunview Hotel, Alagbaka, Akure, Ondo State, ahead of the governorship election in the state on October 10.

RULAAC stated that the suspected thugs had been at the place for about a week.

The group, acting as independent election observers for the governorship election, said the suspected thugs do not look like regular lodgers and appeared suspicious in their outlook and mannerism.

“There are some people lodged at Sunview Hotel, Alagbaka, Akure, for about a week and probably for the next one week.

“They don’t look like regular lodgers. They look suspicious with their mannerisms, outlook and appearances as political thugs, probably kept there for next Saturday’s governorship election. They are mostly lodged at the extension of the hotel,” RULAAC said.

The group urged the police and other security agencies to send a surveillance team to the hotel as a preemptive measure to ensure violence was curtailed before it starts.

Recall that the election campaign has been marred by violence with over 10 incidences recorded by observers and the media.

Yiaga Africa, a non-governmental organisation, has highlighted Akure South, Akoko South-East, Idanre, Owo and Akoko South-West as the local government areas with a high incidence and indicators of violence.

The group predicted that the continued outbreak of violence before the election could lead to a decline in voter turnout during election.

Loading...